Girish Mahajan (Editor)

Set theoretic limit

Updated on
Edit
Like
Comment
Share on FacebookTweet on TwitterShare on LinkedInShare on Reddit

In mathematics, the limit of a sequence of sets A1, A2, ... (subsets of a common set X) is a set whose elements are determined by the sequence in either of two equivalent ways: (1) by upper and lower bounds on the sequence that converge monotonically to the same set (analogous to convergence of real-valued sequences) and (2) by convergence of a sequence of indicator functions which are themselves real-valued. As is the case with sequences of other objects, convergence is not necessary or even usual.

Contents

More generally, again analogous to real-valued sequences, the less restrictive limit infimum and limit supremum of a set sequence always exist and can be used to determine convergence: the limit exists if the limit infimum and limit supremum are identical. (See below). Such set limits are essential in measure theory and probability.

It is a common misconception that the limits infimum and supremum described here involve sets of accumulation points, that is, sets of x = limk→∞xk, where each xk is in some Ank. This is only true if convergence is determined by the discrete metric (that is, xnx iff there is N such that xn = x for all nN). This article is restricted to that situation as it is the only one relevant for measure theory and probability. See the examples below. (On the other hand, there are more general topological notions of set convergence that do involve accumulation points under different metrics or topologies.)

The two definitions

Suppose that { A n } n = 1 is a sequence of sets. The two equivalent definitions are as follows.

  • Using union and intersection, define
  • and If these two sets are equal, then the set-theoretic limit of the sequence An exists and is equal to that common set. Either set as described above can be used to get the limit, and there may be other means to get the limit as well.
  • Using indicator functions, let 1An(x) equal 1 if x is in An and 0 otherwise. Define
  • and where the expressions inside the brackets on the right are, respectively, the limit infimum and limit supremum of the real-valued sequence 1An(x). Again, if these two sets are equal, then the set-theoretic limit of the sequence An exists and is equal to that common set, and either set as described above can be used to get the limit.

    To see the equivalence of the definitions, consider the limit infimum. The use of DeMorgan's rule below explains why this suffices for the limit supremum. Since indicator functions take only values 0 and 1, lim infn→∞ 1An(x) = 1 if and only if 1An(x) takes value 0 only finitely many times. Equivalently, x     n 1   j n A n for some n if and only if there exists n such that the element is in Am for every mn, which is to say if and only if xAn for only finitely many n.

    Therefore, x is in the lim infn→∞ An iff x is in all except finitely many An. For this reason, a shorthand phrase for the limit infimum is "xAn all except finitely often" (or "xAn all but finitely often"), typically expressed by "An a.e.f.o." (or by "An a.b.f.o.").

    Similarly, an element of X is in the limit supremum if, no matter how large n is there exists mn such that the element is in Am. That is, x is in the limit supremum iff x is in infinitely many An. For this reason, a shorthand phrase for the limit supremum is "xAn infinitely often", typically expressed by "An i.o.".

    Monotone sequences

    The sequence {An} is said to be nonincreasing if each An+1An and nondecreasing if each AnAn+1. In each of these cases the set limit exists. Consider, for example, a nonincreasing sequence {An}. Then

    j n A j = j 1 A j  and  j n A j = A n .

    From these it follows that

    lim inf n A n = n 1 j n A j = j 1 A j = n 1 j n A j = lim sup n A n .

    Similarly, if {An} is nondecreasing then

    lim n A n = j 1 A j .

    Properties

  • If the limit of 1An(x), as n goes to infinity, exists for all x then
  • Otherwise, the limit for {An} does not exist.
  • It can be shown that the limit infimum is contained in the limit supremum:
  • for example, simply by observing that xAn all except finitely often implies xAn infinitely often.
  • Using the monotonicity of B n = j n A j and of C n = j n A j ,
  • By using DeMorgan's rule twice, with set complement Ac = XA,
  • That is, xAn all except finitely often is the same as xAn finitely often.
  • From the second definition above and the definitions for limit infimum and limit supremum of a real-valued sequence,
  • and
  • Suppose F is a σ-algebra of subsets of X. That is, F is nonempty and is closed under complement and under unions and intersections of countably many sets. Then, by the first definition above, if each An F then both lim infn → ∞ An and lim supn → ∞ An are elements of F .
  • Examples

  • Let An = (−1/n, 1 − 1/n]. Then
  • and So limn→∞ An = [0, 1) exists.
  • Change the previous example to An = ((−1)n/n, 1 − (−1)n/n]. Then
  • and So limn→∞An does not exist, despite the fact that the left and right endpoints of the intervals converge to 0 and 1, respectively.
  • Let An = {0, 1/n, 2/n, ..., (n−1)/n, 1}. Then
  • (which is all rational numbers between 0 and 1, inclusive) since even for j < n and 0 ≤ kj, k/j = (n×k)/(n×j) is an element of the above. Therefore, lim sup n A n = Q [ 0 , 1 ] . On the other hand, which implies In this case, the sequence A1, A2, ... does not have a limit. Note that lim supn→∞ An is not the set of accumulation points, which would be the entire interval [0, 1] (according to the usual Euclidean metric).

    Probability uses

    Set limits, particularly the limit infimum and the limit supremum, are essential for probability and measure theory. Such limits are used to calculate (or prove) the probabilities and measures of other, more purposeful, sets. For the following, ( X , F , P ) is a probability space, which means F is a σ-algebra of subsets of X and P is a probability measure defined on that σ-algebra. Sets in the σ-algebra are known as events.

    If A1, A2, ... is a sequence of events in F and limn→∞ An exists then

    P ( lim n A n ) = lim n P ( A n ) .

    Borel–Cantelli lemmas

    In probability, the two Borel–Cantelli lemmas can be useful for showing that the limsup of a sequence of events has probability equal to 1 or to 0. The statement of the first (original) Borel–Cantelli lemma is

    if  n = 1 P ( A n ) <  then  P ( lim sup n A n ) = 0.

    The second Borel–Cantelli lemma is a partial converse:

    if  A 1 , A 2 ,  are independent events and  n = 1 P ( A n ) =  then  P ( lim sup n A n ) = 1.

    Almost sure convergence

    One of the most important applications to probability is for demonstrating the almost sure convergence of a sequence of random variables. The event that a sequence of random variables Y1, Y2, ... converges to another random variable Y is formally expressed as { lim sup n | Y n Y | = 0 } . It would be a mistake, however, to write this simply as a limsup of events. That is, this is not the event lim sup n { | Y n Y | = 0 } ! Instead, the complement of the event is

    { lim sup n | Y n Y | 0 } = { lim sup n | Y n Y | > 1 k  for some  k } = k 1 n 1 j n { | Y n Y | > 1 k } = lim k lim sup n { | Y n Y | > 1 k } .

    Therefore,

    P ( { lim sup n | Y n Y | 0 } ) = lim k P ( lim sup n { | Y n Y | > 1 k } ) .

    References

    Set-theoretic limit Wikipedia