Neha Patil (Editor)

Self agency

Updated on
Edit
Like
Comment
Share on FacebookTweet on TwitterShare on LinkedInShare on Reddit

Self-agency, also known as the phenomenal will, is the sense that some actions are self-generated. Scientist Benjamin Libet was the first to study self-agency. He discovered that brain activity predicts the action before one even has conscious awareness of his or her intention to act upon that action. The most influential psychologist in the topic of self-agency was Daniel Wegner, who created the three criteria of self-agency: priority, exclusivity, and consistency.

Contents

According to Wegner, priority means that an action must be planned of being done before the action is initiated. The interval between the action and the effect is known as the intentional binding. Another criteria for self-agency is exclusivity, which means the effect is due to the person’s action and not because of other potential causes for the effect. The last criteria Wegner suggested was consistency. Consistency is the criteria that the one’s planned action must occur as planned.

Internal motor cues are also an indicator in deciding whether an action was used with self-agency and can be measured by the generation of movement. If the predicted sensory state matches the actual sensory state, then self-agency has likely occurred. No models that predict agency have ever been proved.

Self-Agency as inference under uncertainty

Fritz Heider & Mary-Ann Simmel (1944) conducted seminal work on the perception of external causal events. Work on attribution of agency to oneself, however, began with Benjamin Libet's famous demonstration that brain activity predictive of action precedes conscious awareness of the intention to act (Libet, Gleason, Wright, & Pearl 1983; Libet 1985). Since this demonstration psychologists have been trying to determine the relationship between the sense of agency, also known as the phenomenal will, and actual self-agency.

Daniel Wegner’s influential book The Illusion of Conscious Will (Illusion of control; 2002; see also Wegner 2003 and 2004) posits the phenomenal will as the illusory product of post hoc inference. Sense of agency, on this view, is a product of fallible post hoc inference rather than infallible direct access to one’s conscious force of will. The attribution of self-agency is made most strongly when the following three conditions are met: priority, exclusivity, and consistency. Thus, one’s action must be the exclusive potential cause of the event (exclusivity), one must have had prior thoughts or plans about the action before it occurred (priority), and the action the occurred must match the action that was planned (consistency). An inference of self-agency is thus made under at least three parameters of uncertainty.

Uncertainty in Wegner’s three conditions: postdictive accounts of agency

Most studies of self-attribution of agency can be categorized as examining one or more of Wegner’s three conditions of priority, exclusivity, and consistency. By manipulating these three parameters in systematic ways, researchers have shed light on the role that each plays in self-attributions of agency.

Priority

Wegner suggests that temporal order is critical to attributions of self-agency; the agent must have planned or thought about the event/action before it occurred it in order to feel that he has willed it. This is a natural extension of the commonsense notion that a cause cannot occur after its effect. However, a range of findings have shown that, beyond the basic requirement of cause preceding effect, the specifics of the timing are important. Moreover, judgments of timing (and thus priority) can be influenced by variation of other parameters, chiefly Wegner’s consistency condition.

The experience of causing an event alters the subjective experience of their timing. For instance, actions are perceived as temporally shifted towards their effects when they are performed volitionally, but not when involuntarily evoked by transcranial magnetic stimulation (Haggard, Clark, & Kalogeras 2002). This distortion of the perceived interval between movement and effect is known as intentional binding and is considered an implicit measure of the sense of agency. Moore, Wegner, & Haggard (2009) show that supraliminal priming affects intentional binding. This effect contains an inferential ‘‘postdictive” component, because the effect shifts the perceived time of action, even when the probability of the effect’s occurrence is low (Moore & Haggard, 2008).

Gentsch & Schütz-Bosbach (2011) find top–down modulation of visual event-related potentials (ERPs) by both self agency and priming of self-agency, suggesting that both efferent information and prior thoughts about action consequence inform the sense of agency. Furthermore, Engbert et al. (2008) showed that intentional binding occurred only when the movement of the response lever was actively generated by the subject; passive movements (initiated by the response lever) did not result in intentional binding. They take these results to suggest that efferent motor commands, rather than just priority and consistency (see below), is key to self-agency attributions.

Intentional binding may not be exclusive to self-agency, however; Strother, House, & Sukhvinder (2010) found intentional binding in a shared action situation where other agents with similar goals and actions were present.

Exclusivity

Wegner’s exclusivity condition posits that attribution of self-agency occurs most strongly in the absence of other potential causes. The presence of other potential causes in temporal and spatial proximity to the event will, all else being equal, result in a diminished sense of self-agency.

Dijksterhuis and colleagues (2008) found that nonconscious priming with first-person singular pronouns increased feelings of self-agency, while nonconscious priming with other potential causes (computer, God) decreased feelings of self-agency. Hindriks et al. (2011) have proposed a computational Bayesian inference model of self-attribution of agency that deals mainly with the exclusivity dimension. (For another Bayesian approach to agency and control, see Huys & Dayan, 2009.)

Consistency

Wegner argues that the event must match the planned action; attribution will be low if the outcome does not match the perceived cause.

Wegner & Wheatley (1999) demonstrated that priming participants with thoughts relevant to a movement just before it was made by another person caused participants to feel they had caused the action themselves. Ebert & Wegner (2010) also showed that manipulating consistency enhanced both judgments of self-authorship and temporal binding between cause and effect (see also Haggard, Clark, & Kalogeras, 2002; Moore, Wegner, & Haggard, 2009).

Other studies have shown that consistency between prior thought and subsequent action can produce a sense of vicarious agency for another person’s actions (Wegner, Sparrow, & Winerman, 2004), increase self-agency attributions for one's own actions (Pronin, Wegner, McCarthy, & Rodriguez, 2006), and even produce changes in self-attribution when the prior thought is unconscious (Aarts, Custers, & Wegner, 2005) or the result of nonconscious priming (Aarts, Custers, & Marien, 2009).

Internal motor cues: predictive accounts of agency

Wegner’s account is a leading example of a postdictive or inferential account of the attribution of self-agency. On this type of view, the feeling of self-agency emerges entirely from post hoc inference and does not track or emerge from anything directly related to the actual causation of the action.

Computational models of motor control, by contrast, hypothesize that the sense of agency for a given action arises most directly from internal motor representations associated with generating the movement. An internal forward model based on efference copy, for example, can predict the sensory consequences of a motor command and compare them with the actual sensory state after that action has been initiated (Blakemore, Wolpert, & Frith, 2000, 2002; Haggard, 2005). If the actual sensory state matches the predicted one, self-agency is (likely to be) inferred. Indeed, the intentional binding effect (described above) may depend on the motor efference command; Engbert, Wohlschläger, & Haggard (2008) provide data suggesting that compression of estimated intervals between action and effect occurs only for volitional actions initiated by the self and not for passive actions or for actions performed by others. These authors maintain an efferent motor command is necessary for a sense of agency. Indeed, omitting the effect of an action does eliminate intentional binding, so long as the probability of an effect given an action is sufficiently high (Moore & Haggard, 2008).

Attempts to Synthesize Predictive and Postdictive Accounts of Agency

Synofzik, Vosgerau, & Newen (2008) review findings on comparator models and argue that they cannot account for either a feeling of agency or a judgment of agency. Their multifactorial model separates feeling from judgment and discusses the conceptual level of processing that is added to the latter. Their discussion concerns explicit judgments of agency, however, which may differ from results obtained using implicit measures (e.g., Engbert, Wohlschläger, & Haggard 2008).

Moore, Lagnado, Deal, & Haggard (2009) investigated whether statistical contingency alone could explain both predictive and inferential ‘‘postdictive” intentional binding effects. Both predictive and ‘postdictive' shifts in the time of action perception depended on strong contingency between the action and effect, suggesting that the experience of agency involves causal learning based on statistical contingency.

Although predictive and postdictive accounts of agency are often cast as competitors, they may in fact be reconcilable when attributions of self-agency are viewed within the framework of cognition under uncertainty. In particular, a comparator model based on efference copy can be seen as a more sophisticated way of characterizing Wegner’s consistency parameter and the computations that are likely to be a part of it. Basing outcome predictions on motor commands, rather than just higher-level representations of the goal state that an action is intended to bring about, is likely to provide finer-grained predictions with which to compare outcomes, thereby reducing uncertainty in agency attributions. This higher predictive resolution, in turn, could be useful in making exclusivity judgments (Wegner’s second condition): even if a particular goal state is brought about, if the way it is brought about does not closely match the motoric prediction, the attribution of agency may be reduced or blocked entirely. Similarly, given evidence (discussed above – see Haggard, Clark, & Kalogeras 2002) that whether or not an action is volitional affects intentional binding, motoric representations and predictions seem also to affect Wegner’s priority parameter. As such, predictive and postdictive accounts may simply differ in emphasis and in the level at which they describe the phenomenon (viz., attribution of agency), rather than being fundamentally incompatible.

Citations

Aarts H, Custers R, & Marien H (2009). Priming and Authorship Ascription: When Nonconscious Goals Turn Into Conscious Experiences of Self-Agency. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 96, 967-979.

Aarts H, Custers R, & Wegner DM (2005). On the inference of personal authorship: Enhancing experienced agency by priming effect information. Consciousness and Cognition, 14, 439–458.

Blakemore S-J, Wolpert DM, & Frith CD (2000). Why can’t you tickle yourself? Neuroreport, 11, 11–16.

Blakemore S-J, Wolpert DM, & Frith CD (2002). Abnormalities in the awareness of action. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6(6), 237–242.

Dijksterhuis A, Preson J, Wegner D, & Aarts H (2008). Effects of subliminal priming of self and God on self-attribution of authorship for events. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 44, 2-9.

Engbert K, Wohlschläger A, & Haggard P (2008). Who is causing what? The sense of agency is relational and efferent-triggered. Cognition, 107, 693–704.

Gentsch A & Schütz-Bosbach S (2011). I Did It: Unconscious Expectation of Sensory Consequences Modulates the Experience of Self-agency and Its Functional Signature. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 23(12), 3817-3828.

Haggard P, Clark S, & Kalogeras J (2002). Voluntary action and conscious awareness. Nature Neuroscience, 5(4), 382–385.

Haggard, P. (2005). Conscious intention and motor cognition. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 9(6), 290-295.

Heider F & Simmel MA (1944). An experimental study of apparent behavior. American Journal of Psychology, 57, 243–249.

Hindriks K, Wiggers P, Jonker C, & Haselager W (2011). Towards a Computational Model of the Self-attribution of Agency. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, 6703, 295-305.

Huys QJM, & Dayan P (2009). A Bayesian formulation of behavioral control. Cognition, 113, 314-328.

Libet B, Gleason CA, Wright EW, & Pearl DK (1983). Time of conscious intention to act in relation to onset of cerebral activity (readiness-potential) – the unconscious initiation of a freely voluntary act. Brain, 106, 623–642.

Libet B (1985). Unconscious cerebral initiative and the role of conscious will in voluntary action. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 8, 529–566.

Moore J & Haggard P (2008). Awareness of action: Inference and prediction. Consciousness and Cognition, 17(1), 136-144.

Moore J, Wegner DM, & Haggard P (2009). Modulating the sense of agency with external cues. Consciousness and Cognition, 18(4), 1056-1064.

Moore JW, Lagnado D, Deal DC, & Haggard P (2009). Feelings of control: Contingency determines experience of action. Cognition, 110, 279–283.

Pronin E, Wegner DM, McCarthy K, & Rodriguez S (2006). Everyday magical powers: The role of apparent mental causation in the overestimation of personal influence. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 91, 218–231.

Strother L, House KA, & Sukhvinder SO (2010). Subjective agency and awareness of shared actions. Consciousness and Cognition, 19, 12–20.

Synofzik M, Vosgerau G, & Newen A (2008). Beyond the comparator model: A multifactorial two-step account of agency. Consciousness and Cognition, 17, 219–239.

Wegner DM (2002). The Illusion of Conscious Will. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.

Wegner DM (2004). Précis of The illusion of conscious will. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27(5), 649-679.

Wegner DM (2003). The mind’s best trick: how we experience conscious will. Trends in Cognitive Science, 7(2), 65-69).

Wegner DM, & Wheatley T (1999). Apparent mental causation: Sources of the experience of will. American Psychologist, 54(7), 480–492.

Wegner DM, Sparrow B, & Winerman L (2004). Vicarious Agency: Experiencing Control Over the Movements of Others. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 86(8), 838-848.

References

Self-agency Wikipedia