Kalpana Kalpana (Editor)

Resource monotonicity

Updated on
Edit
Like
Comment
Share on FacebookTweet on TwitterShare on LinkedInShare on Reddit

Resource monotonicity (RM; aka aggregate monotonicity) is a principle of fair division. It says that, if there are more resources to share, then all agents should be weakly better off; no agent should lose from the increase in resources. The RM principle has been studied in various division problems.

Contents

Allocation of a single continuous resource

Suppose society has t units of some divisible resource (e.g. wood, medication, etc.). The resource should be divided among n agents with different utilities. The utility of agent i is represented by a function u i ; when agent i receives y i units of resource, he derives from it a utility of u i ( y i ) . Society has to decide how to divide the resource among the agents, i.e, to find a vector y 1 , , y n such that: y 1 + + y n = t .

Two classic allocation rules are the egalitarian rule - aiming to equalize the utilities of all agents (equivalently: maximize the minimum utility), and the utilitarian rule - aiming to maximize the sum of utilities.

The egalitarian rule is always RM: when there is more resource to share, the minimum utility that can be guaranteed to all agents increases, and all agents equally share the increase. In contrast, the utilitarian rule might be not RM.

For example, suppose there are two agents, Alice and Bob, with the following utilities:

The egalitarian allocation is found by solving the equation: y A 2 = ( t y A ) , which is equivalent to t = y A 2 + y A , so y A is monotonically increasing with t . An equivalent equation is: y B = ( t y B ) 2 , which is equivalent to t = y B + y B , so y B too is monotonically increasing with t . So in this example (as always) the egalitarian rule is RM.

In contrast, the utilitarian rule is not RM. This is because Alice has increasing returns: her marginal utility is small when she has few resources, but it increases fast when she has many resources. Hence, when the total amount of resource is small (specifically, t < 1 ), the utilitarian sum is maximized when all resources are given to Bob; but when there are many resources ( t > 1 ), the maximum is attained when all resources are given to Alice. Mathematically, if y is the amount given to Alice, then the utilitarian sum is y 2 + ( t y ) . This function has only an internal minimum point but not an internal maximum point; its maximum point in the range [ 0 , t ] is attained in one of the endpoints. It is the left endpoint when t < 1 and the right endpoint when t > 1 . In general, the utilitarian allocation rule is RM when all agents have diminishing returns, but it may be not RM when some agents have increasing returns (as in the example).

Thus, if society uses the utilitarian rule to allocate resources, then Bob loses value when the amount of resources increases. This is bad because it gives Bob an incentive against economic growth: Bob will try to keep the total amount small in order to keep his own share large.

Allocation of a single discrete resource

The leximin rule (maximizing the lexicographic ordering of utilities) might be not RM when the resource to divide consists of several indivisible units. For example, suppose there are t tennis rackets. Alice enjoys using even a single racket (for playing against the wall), but Bob and Carl only enjoy using two rackets (for playing against each other or against Alice). Hence, if there is only a single racket, the leximin allocation gives it entirely to Alice, while if there are two rackets, they are divided equally between the agents (each agent gets a racket for 2/3 of the time). Hence, Alice loses utility when the total amount of rackets increases. Alice has an incentive to oppose growth.

Facility location game

In this setting, the social choice question is where a certain facility should be located. Consider the following network of roads, where the letters denote junctions and the numbers denote distances:

The population is distributed uniformly along the roads. People want to be as close as possible to the facility, so they have "dis-utility" (negative utility) measured by their distance to the facility.

In the initial situation, the egalitarian rule locates the facility at C, since it minimizes the maximum distance to the facility and sets it to 11 (the utilitarian and Nash rules also locate the facility at C).

Now, there is a new junction X and some new roads:

The egalitarian rule now locates the facility at X, since it allows to decrease the maximum distance from 11 to 9 (the utilitarian and Nash rules also locate the facility at X).

The increase in resources helped most people, but decreased the utility of those living in or near C.

Economic growth with falling real wages

A blog post shows that, in the years 2008-2014, the United Kingdom has enjoyed country-wide economic growth, while the real wages declined. This apparently shows that the economic system in the UK is not resource-monotonic: the total amount of resources increases while most workers lose utility.

Bargaining

An monotonicity axiom closely related to resource-monotonicity appeared first in the context of the bargaining problem. A bargaining problem is defined by a set of alternatives; a bargaining solution should select a single alternative from the set, subject to some axioms. The resource-monotonicity axiom was presented in two variants:

  1. "If, for every utility level that player 1 may demand, the maximum feasible utility level that player 2 can simultaneously reach is increased, then the utility level assigned to player 2 according to the solution should also be increased". This axiom leads to a characterization of the Kalai–Smorodinsky bargaining solution.
  2. "Let T and S be bargaining games; if T contains S then for all agents, the utility in T is weakly larger than the utility in S". In other words, if the set of alternatives grows, the selected solution should be at least as good for all agents as the previous solution. This axiom, in addition to Pareto optimality and symmetry and Independence of irrelevant alternatives, leads to a characterization of the egalitarian bargaining solution.

References

Resource monotonicity Wikipedia