Dependence logic is a logical formalism, created by Jouko Väänänen, which adds dependence atoms to the language of first-order logic. A dependence atom is an expression of the form
Contents
- Syntax
- Terms
- Atomic formulas
- Complex formulas and sentences
- Conjunction and universal quantification
- Semantics
- Teams
- Positive and negative satisfaction
- Semantic rules
- Positive satisfiability
- Negative satisfiability
- Dependence logic and first order logic
- Dependence logic and second order logic
- Dependence logic and branching quantifiers
- Dependence logic and IF logic
- Properties
- Complexity
- Team logic
- Modal dependence logic
- Intuitionistic dependence logic
- Independence logic
- Inclusionexclusion logic
- Generalized quantifiers
- References
Dependence logic is a logic of imperfect information, like branching quantifier logic or independence-friendly logic: in other words, its game theoretic semantics can be obtained from that of first-order logic by restricting the availability of information to the players, thus allowing for non-linearly ordered patterns of dependence and independence between variables. However, dependence logic differs from these logics in that it separates the notions of dependence and independence from the notion of quantification.
Syntax
The syntax of dependence logic is an extension of that of first-order logic. For a fixed signature σ = (Sfunc, Srel, ar), the set of all well-formed dependence logic formulas is defined according to the following rules:
Terms
Terms in dependence logic are defined precisely as in first-order logic.
Atomic formulas
There are three types of atomic formulas in dependence logic:
- A relational atom is an expression of the form
R t 1 … t n R in our signature and for any n-uple of termst 1 … t n - An equality atom is an expression of the form
t 1 = t 2 t 1 t 2 - A dependence atom is an expression of the form
= ( t 1 … t n ) , for anyn ∈ N and for any n-uple of termst 1 … t n
Nothing else is an atomic formula of dependence logic.
Relational and equality atoms are also called first order atoms.
Complex formulas and sentences
For a fixed signature σ, the set of all formulas
- Any atomic formula
ϕ is a formula, andFree ( ϕ ) is the set of all variables occurring in it; - If
ϕ is a formula, so is¬ ϕ andFree ( ¬ ϕ ) = Free ( ϕ ) ; - If
ϕ andψ are formulas, so isϕ ∨ ψ andFree ( ϕ ∨ ψ ) = Free ( ϕ ) ∪ Free ( ψ ) ; - If
ϕ is a formula andx is a variable,∃ x ϕ is also a formula andFree ( ∃ v ϕ ) = Free ( ϕ ) ∖ { v } .
Nothing is a dependence logic formula unless it can be obtained through a finite number of applications of these four rules.
A formula
Conjunction and universal quantification
In the above presentation of the syntax of dependence logic, conjunction and universal quantification are not treated as primitive operators; rather, they are defined in terms of disjunction and negation and existential quantification respectively, by means of De Morgan's Laws.
Therefore,
Semantics
The team semantics for dependence logic is a variant of Wilfrid Hodges' compositional semantics for IF logic. There exist equivalent game-theoretic semantics for dependence logic, both in terms of imperfect information games and in terms of perfect information games.
Teams
Let
It may be helpful to visualize such a team as a database relation with attributes
Positive and negative satisfaction
Team semantics can be defined in terms of two relations
Given a structure
If
The necessity of considering positive and negative satisfaction separately is a consequence of the fact that in dependence logic, as in the logic of branching quantifiers or in IF logic, the law of the excluded middle does not hold; alternatively, one may assume that all formulas are in negation normal form, using De Morgan's relations in order to define universal quantification and conjunction from existential quantification and disjunction respectively, and consider positive satisfaction alone.
Given a sentence
Semantic rules
As for the case of Alfred Tarski's satisfiability relation for first-order formulas, the positive and negative satisfiability relations of the team semantics for dependence logic are defined by structural induction over the formulas of the language. Since the negation operator interchanges positive and negative satisfiability, the two inductions corresponding to
Positive satisfiability
-
A ⊨ X + R t 1 … t n -
R is a n-ary symbol in the signature ofA ; - All variables occurring in the terms
t 1 … t n X ; - For every assignment
μ ∈ X , the evaluation of the tuple( t 1 … t n ) according toμ is in the interpretation ofR inA ;
-
-
A ⊨ X + t 1 = t 2 - All variables occurring in the terms
t 1 t 2 X ; - For every assignment
μ ∈ X , the evaluations oft 1 t 2 A are the same;
- All variables occurring in the terms
-
A ⊨ X + = ( t 1 … t n ) if and only if any two assignmentss , s ′ ∈ X whose evaluations of the tuple( t 1 … t n − 1 ) coincide assign the same value tot n -
A ⊨ X + ¬ ϕ if and only ifA ⊨ X − ϕ ; -
A ⊨ X + ϕ ∨ ψ if and only if there exist teamsY andZ such that-
X = Y ∪ Z ' -
A ⊨ Y + ϕ ; -
A ⊨ Z + ψ ;
-
-
A ⊨ X + ∃ x ϕ if and only if there exists a functionF fromX to the domain ofA such thatA ⊨ X [ F / x ] + ϕ , whereX [ F / x ] = { s [ F ( s ) / x ] : s ∈ X } .
Negative satisfiability
-
A ⊨ X − R t 1 … t n -
R is a n-ary symbol in the signature ofA ; - All variables occurring in the terms
t 1 … t n X ; - For every assignment
μ ∈ X , the evaluation of the tuple( t 1 … t n ) according toμ is not in the interpretation ofR inA ;
-
-
A ⊨ X − t 1 = t 2 - All variables occurring in the terms
t 1 t 2 X ; - For every assignment
μ ∈ X , the evaluations oft 1 t 2 A are different;
- All variables occurring in the terms
-
A ⊨ X − = ( t 1 … t n ) if and only ifX is the empty team; -
A ⊨ X − ¬ ϕ if and only ifA ⊨ X + ϕ ; -
A ⊨ X − ϕ ∨ ψ if and only ifA ⊨ X − ϕ andA ⊨ X − ψ ; -
A ⊨ X − ∃ x ϕ if and only ifA ⊨ X [ A / x ] − ϕ , whereX [ A / x ] = { s [ m / x ] : s ∈ A } andA is the domain ofA .
Dependence logic and first-order logic
Dependence logic is a conservative extension of first-order logic: in other words, for every first order sentence
However, dependence logic is strictly more expressive than first order logic: for example, the sentence
is true in a model
Dependence logic and second-order logic
Every dependence logic sentence is equivalent to some sentence in the existential fragment of second-order logic, that is, to some second-order sentence of the form
where
As for open formulas, dependence logic corresponds to the downwards monotone fragment of existential second-order logic, in the sense that a nonempty class of teams is definable by a dependence logic formula if and only if the corresponding class of relations is downwards monotone and definable by an existential second-order formula.
Dependence logic and branching quantifiers
Branching quantifiers are expressible in terms of dependence atoms: for example, the expression
is equivalent to the dependence logic sentence
Conversely, any dependence logic sentence is equivalent to some sentence in the logic of branching quantifiers, since all existential second-order sentences are expressible in branching quantifier logic.
Dependence logic and IF logic
Any dependence logic sentence is logically equivalent to some IF logic sentence, and vice versa.
However, the issue is subtler when it comes to open formulas. Translations between IF logic and dependence logic formulas, and vice versa, exist as long as the domain of the team is fixed: in other words, for all sets of variables
for all structures
for all structures
Properties
Dependence logic formulas are downwards closed: if
The law of the excluded middle fails in dependence logic: for example, the formula
Both the compactness theorem and the Löwenheim-Skolem theorem are true for dependence logic. Craig's interpolation theorem also holds, but, due to the nature of negation in dependence logic, in a slightly modified formulation: if two dependence logic formulas
As IF logic, Dependence logic can define its own truth operator: more precisely, there exists a formula
This does not contradict Tarski's undefinability theorem, since the negation of dependence logic is not the usual contradictory one.
Complexity
As a consequence of Fagin's theorem, the properties of finite structures definable in dependence logic correspond exactly to NP properties. Furthermore, Durand and Kontinen showed that restricting the number of universal quantifiers or the arity of dependence atoms in sentences gives rise to hierarchy theorems with respect to expressive power.
The inconsistency problem of dependence logic is semidecidable, and in fact equivalent to the inconsistency problem for first-order logic. However, the decision problem for dependence logic is non-arithmetical, and is in fact complete with respect to the
Team logic
Team logic extends dependence logic with a contradictory negation
Modal dependence logic
The dependence atom, or a suitable variant thereof, can be added to the language of modal logic, thus obtaining modal dependence logic.
Intuitionistic dependence logic
As it is, dependence logic lacks an implication. The intuitionistic implication
Intuitionistic dependence logic, that is, dependence logic supplemented with the intuitionistic implication, is equivalent to second-order logic.
Independence logic
Instead of dependence atoms, independence logic adds to the language of first-order logic independence atoms
Independence logic corresponds to existential second-order logic, in the sense that a non-empty class of teams is definable by an independence logic formula if and only if the corresponding class of relations is definable by an existential second-order formula. Therefore, on the level of open formulas, independence logic is strictly stronger in expressive power than dependence logic. However, on the level of sentences these logics are equivalent.
Inclusion/exclusion logic
Inclusion/exclusion logic extends first-order logic with inclusion atoms
Inclusion/exclusion logic has the same expressive power as independence logic, already on the level of open formulas. Inclusion logic and exclusion logic are obtained by adding only inclusion atoms or exclusion atoms to first-order logic, respectively. Inclusion logic sentences correspond in expressive power to greatest fixed-point logic sentences; hence inclusion logic captures (least) fixed-point logic on finite models, and PTIME over finite ordered models. Exclusion logic in turn corresponds to dependence logic in expressive power.
Generalized quantifiers
Another way of extending dependence logic is to add some generalized quantifiers to the language of dependence logic. Very recently there has been some study of dependence logic with monotone generalized quantifiers and dependence logic with a certain majority quantifier, the latter leading to a new descriptive complexity characterization of the counting hierarchy.