![]() | ||
In logic, contraposition is an inference that says that a conditional statement is logically equivalent to its contrapositive. The contrapositive of the statement has its antecedent and consequent inverted and flipped: the contrapositive of
Contents
- Intuitive explanation
- Formal definition
- Simple proof by definition of a conditional
- Simple proof by contradiction
- More rigorous proof of the equivalence of contrapositives
- Examples
- Truth
- Application
- References
The contrapositive can be compared with three other relationships between conditional statements:
Note that if
Intuitive explanation
Consider the Euler diagram shown. According to this diagram, if something is in A, it must be in B as well. So we can interpret "all of A is in B" as:
It is also clear that anything that is not within B (the blue region) cannot be within A, either. This statement,
is the contrapositive. Therefore, we can say that
Practically speaking, this may make life much easier when trying to prove something. For example, if we want to prove that every girl in the United States (A) has brown hair (B), we can try to directly prove
To conclude, for any statement where A implies B, then not B always implies not A. Proving or disproving either one of these statements automatically proves or disproves the other. They are fully equivalent.
Formal definition
A proposition Q is implicated by a proposition P when the following relationship holds:
This states that, "if P, then Q", or, "if Socrates is a man, then Socrates is human." In a conditional such as this, P is the antecedent, and Q is the consequent. One statement is the contrapositive of the other only when its antecedent is the negated consequent of the other, and vice versa. The contrapositive of the example is
That is, "If not-Q, then not-P", or, more clearly, "If Q is not the case, then P is not the case." Using our example, this is rendered "If Socrates is not human, then Socrates is not a man." This statement is said to be contraposed to the original and is logically equivalent to it. Due to their logical equivalence, stating one effectively states the other; when one is true, the other is also true. Likewise with falsity.
Strictly speaking, a contraposition can only exist in two simple conditionals. However, a contraposition may also exist in two complex conditionals, if they are similar. Thus,
Simple proof by definition of a conditional
In first-order logic, the conditional is defined as:
We have:
Simple proof by contradiction
Let:
It is given that, if A is true, then B is true, and it is also given that B is not true. We can then show that A must not be true by contradiction. For, if A were true, then B would have to also be true (given). However, it is given that B is not true, so we have a contradiction. Therefore, A is not true (assuming that we are dealing with concrete statements that are either true or not true):
We can apply the same process the other way round:
We also know that B is either true or not true. If B is not true, then A is also not true. However, it is given that A is true; so, the assumption that B is not true leads to contradiction and must be false. Therefore, B must be true:
Combining the two proved statements makes them logically equivalent:
More rigorous proof of the equivalence of contrapositives
Logical equivalence between two propositions means that they are true together or false together. To prove that contrapositives are logically equivalent, we need to understand when material implication is true or false.
This is only false when P is true and Q is false. Therefore, we can reduce this proposition to the statement "False when P and not-Q" (i.e. "True when it is not the case that P and not-Q"):
The elements of a conjunction can be reversed with no effect (by commutativity):
We define
This reads "It is not the case that (R is true and S is false)", which is the definition of a material conditional. We can then make this substitution:
When we swap our definitions of R and S, we arrive at the following:
Examples
Take the statement "All red objects have color." This can be equivalently expressed as "If an object is red, then it has color."
In other words, the contrapositive is logically equivalent to a given conditional statement, though not sufficient for a biconditional.
Similarly, take the statement "All quadrilaterals have four sides," or equivalently expressed "If a polygon is a quadrilateral, then it has four sides."
Since the statement and the converse are both true, it is called a biconditional, and can be expressed as "A polygon is a quadrilateral if, and only if, it has four sides." (The phrase if and only if is sometimes abbreviated iff.) That is, having four sides is both necessary to be a quadrilateral, and alone sufficient to deem it a quadrilateral.
Truth
Application
Because the contrapositive of a statement always has the same truth value (truth or falsity) as the statement itself, it can be a powerful tool for proving mathematical theorems. A proof by contraposition (contrapositive) is a direct proof of the contrapositive of a statement. However, indirect methods such as proof by contradiction can also be used with contraposition, as, for example, in the proof of the irrationality of the square root of 2. By the definition of a rational number, the statement can be made that "If
The previous example employed the contrapositive of a definition to prove a theorem. One can also prove a theorem by proving the contrapositive of the theorem's statement. To prove that if a positive integer N is a non-square number, its square root is irrational, we can equivalently prove its contrapositive, that if a positive integer N has a square root that is rational, then N is a square number. This can be shown by setting √N equal to the rational expression a/b with a and b being positive integers with no common prime factor, and squaring to obtain N = a2/b2 and noting that since N is a positive integer b=1 so that N = a2, a square number.