Suvarna Garge (Editor)

Cumulativity

Updated on
Edit
Like
Comment
Share on FacebookTweet on TwitterShare on LinkedInShare on Reddit

In linguistic semantics, an expression X is said to have cumulative reference if and only if the following holds: If X is true of both of a and b, then it is also true of the combination of a and b. Example: If two separate entities can be said to be "water", then combining them into one entity will yield more "water". If two separate entities can be said to be "a house", their combination cannot be said to be "a house". Hence, "water" has cumulative reference, while the expression "a house" does not. The plural form "houses", however, does have cumulative reference. If two (groups of) entities are both "houses", then their combination will still be "houses".

Cumulativity has proven relevant to the linguistic treatment of the mass/count distinction and for the characterization of grammatical telicity.

Formally, a cumulativity predicate CUM can be defined as follows, where capital X is a variable over sets, U is the universe of discourse, p is a mereological part structure on U, and p is the mereological sum operation.

( X U p ) ( C U M ( X ) x , y ( X ( x ) X ( y ) x y ) x , y ( X ( x ) X ( y ) X ( x p y ) ) )

In later work, Krifka has generalized the notion to n-ary predicates, based on the phenomenon of cumulative quantification. For example, the two following sentences appear to be equivalent:

John ate an apple and Mary ate a pear. John and Mary ate an apple and a pear.

This shows that the relation "eat" is cumulative. In general, an n-ary predicate R is cumulative if and only if the following holds:

( x 1 , , x n , y 1 , , y n ) ( R ( x 1 , , x n ) R ( y 1 , , y n ) ) R ( x 1 y 1 , , x n y n )

( x 1 , , x n , y 1 , , y n ) ( R ( x 1 , , x n ) R ( y 1 , , y n ) ) R ( x 1 y 1 , , x n y n )

References

Cumulativity Wikipedia