In calculus, the (ε, δ)-definition of limit ("epsilon–delta definition of limit") is a formalization of the notion of limit. The concept is due to Augustin-Louis Cauchy, who never gave an (
Contents
History
Although the Greeks examined limiting process, such as the Babylonian method, they probably had no concept similar to the modern limit. The need for the concept of a limit came into force in the 17th century when Pierre de Fermat attempted to find the slope of the tangent line at a point
The key to the above calculation is that since
This problem reappeared later in the 1600s at the center of the development of calculus because calculations such as Fermat's are important to the calculation of derivatives. Isaac Newton first developed calculus via an infinitesimal quantity called a fluxion. He developed them in reference to the idea of an "infinitely small moment in time..." However, Netwon later rejected fluxions in favor of a theory of ratios that is close to the modern
Additionally, Newton occasionally explained limits in terms similar to the epsilon–delta definition. Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz developed an infinitesimal of his own and tried to provide it with a rigorous footing, but it was still greeted with unease by some mathematicians and philosophers.
Augustin-Louis Cauchy gave a definition of limit in terms of a more primitive notion he called a variable quantity. He never gave an epsilon–delta definition of limit (Grabiner 1981). Some of Cauchy's proofs contain indications of the epsilon–delta method. Whether or not his foundational approach can be considered a harbinger of Weierstrass's is a subject of scholarly dispute. Grabiner feels that it is, while Schubring (2005) disagrees. Nakane concludes that Cauchy and Weierstrass gave the same name to different notions of limit.
Eventually, Weierstrass and Bolzano are credited with providing a rigorous footing for calculus in the form of the modern
This is not to say that the limiting definition was free of problems as although it removed the need to use infinitesimals, it did require the construction of the real numbers by Richard Dedekind. This is also not to say that infinitesimals have no place in modern mathematics as later mathematicians were able to rigorously create infinitesimal quantities as part of the hyperreal number or surreal number systems. Moreover, it is possible to rigorously develop calculus with these quantities and they have other mathematical uses.
Informal statement
A viable intuitive or provisional definition is that a "function f approaches the limit L near a (symbolically,
When we say that two things are close (such as f(x) and L or x and a) we mean that the distance between them is small. When f(x), L, x, and a are real numbers, distance is the absolute value of one quantity minus the other. Thus, when we say f(x) is close to L we mean
When we say that we can make f(x) as close as we like to L, we mean that for all non-zero distances,
When we say that we can make f(x) as close as we like to L by requiring that x be sufficiently close to, but, unequal to, a, we mean that for all non-zero distances
The aspect that must be grasped is that the definition requires the following conversation. One is provided with any challenge
Precise statement for real valued functions
The
Let
if for every
Symbolically:
If
Precise statement for functions between metric spaces
The definition can be generalized to functions that map between metric spaces. These spaces come with a function, called a metric, that takes two points in the space and returns a real number that represents the distance between the two points. The generalized definition is as follows:
Suppose
We say that
if for every
Since
Negation of the precise statement
The negation of the definition is a follows:
Suppose
We say that
if there exists an
We say that
For the negation of a real valued function defined on the real numbers, simply set
Precise statement for limits at infinity
The precise statement for limits at infinity is as follows:
Suppose
We say that
if for every
Example 1
We will show that
We let
Since sine is bounded above by 1 and below by -1,
Thus, if we take
Example 2
Let us prove the statement that
for any real number
Let
We start by factoring:
We recognize that
So we suppose
Thus,
Thus via the triangle inequality,
Thus, if we further suppose that
then
In summary, we set
So, if
Thus, we have found a
for any real number
Example 3
Let us prove the statement that
This is easily shown through graphical understandings of the limit, and as such serves as a strong basis for introduction to proof. According to the formal definition above, a limit statement is correct if and only if confining
to
Simplifying, factoring, and dividing 3 on the right hand side of the implication yields
which immediately gives the required result if we choose
Thus the proof is completed. The key to the proof lies in the ability of one to choose boundaries in
Continuity
A function f is said to be continuous at c if it is both defined at c and its value at c equals the limit of f as x approaches c:
If the condition 0 < |x − c| is left out of the definition of limit, then requiring f(x) to have a limit at c would be the same as requiring f(x) to be continuous at c.
f is said to be continuous on an interval I if it is continuous at every point c of I.
Comparison with infinitesimal definition
Keisler proved that a hyperreal definition of limit reduces the quantifier complexity by two quantifiers. Namely,